Semantics
is the study of the meaning of linguistic expressions. The language can be a
natural language, such as English or Navajo, or an artificial language, like a
computer programming language. Meaning in natural languages is mainly studied
by linguists. In fact, semantics is one of the main branches of contemporary
linguistics. Theoretical computer scientists and logicians think about
artificial languages. In some areas of computer science, these divisions are
crossed. In machine translation, for instance, computer scientists may want to
relate natural language texts to abstract representations of their meanings; to
do this, they have to design artificial languages for representing meanings.
There
are strong connections to philosophy. Earlier in this century, much work in
semantics was done by philosophers, and some important work is still done by
philosophers.
Anyone
who speaks a language has a truly amazing capacity to reason about the meanings
of texts. Take, for instance, the sentence
(S) I can't untie that knot with one
hand.
Even
though you have probably never seen this sentence, you can easily see things
like the following:
1.
The sentence is about the abilities
of whoever spoke or wrote it. (Call this person the speaker.)
2.
It's also about a knot, maybe one
that the speaker is pointing at.
3.
The sentence denies that the speaker
has a certain ability. (This is the contribution of the word ‘can't'.)
4.
Untying is a way of making something
not tied.
5.
The sentence doesn't mean that the
knot has one hand; it has to do with how many hands are used to do the untying.
The
meaning of a sentence is not just an unordered heap of the meanings of its words.
If that were true, then ‘Cowboys ride horses’ and ‘Horses ride cowboys’ would
mean the same thing. So we need to think about arrangements of meanings.
Here
is an arrangement that seems to bring out the relationships of the meanings in
sentence (S).
Not
[ I [ Able [ [ [Make [Not [Tied]]] [That knot ] ] [With One Hand] ] ] ]
The
unit [Make [Not [Tied]] here corresponds to the act of untying; it contains a
subunit corresponding to the state of being untied. Larger units correspond to
the act of untying-that-knot and to the act to-untie-that-knot-with-one-hand.
Then this act combines with Able to make a larger unit, corresponding to the
state of being-able-to-untie-that-knot-with-one-hand. This unit combines with I
to make the thought that I have this state -- that is, the thought that
I-am-able-to-untie-that-knot-with-one-hand. Finally, this combines with Not and
we get the denial of that thought.
This
idea that meaningful units combine systematically to form larger meaningful
units, and understanding sentences is a way of working out these combinations,
has probably been the most important theme in contemporary semantics.
Linguists
who study semantics look for general rules that bring out the relationship
between form, which is
the observed arrangement of words in sentences and meaning. This is interesting
and challenging, because these relationships are so complex.
A
semantic rule for English might say that a simple sentence involving the word
‘can't’ always corresponds to a meaning arrangement like
Not
[ Able ... ],
but
never to one like
Able
[ Not ... ].
For
instance, ‘I can't dance’ means that I'm unable to dance; it doesn't mean that
I'm able not to dance.
To
assign meanings to the sentences of a language, you need to know what they are.
It is the job of another area of linguistics, called syntax, to
answer this question, by providing rules that show how sentences and other
expressions are built up out of smaller parts, and eventually out of words. The
meaning of a sentence depends not only on the words it contains, but on its
syntactic makeup: the sentence
(S) That can hurt you,
for
instance, is ambiguous -- it has two distinct meanings.
These correspond to two distinct syntactic
structures. In one structure ‘That’ is the
subject and ‘can’ is an auxiliary verb (meaning “able”), and in the other ‘That
can’ is the subject and ‘can’ is a noun (indicating a sort of container).
Because
the meaning of a sentence depends so closely on its syntactic structure,
linguists have given a lot of thought to the relations between syntactic
structure and meaning; in fact, evidence about ambiguity is one way of testing
ideas about syntactic structure.
You
would expect an expert in semantics to know a lot about what meanings are. But
linguists haven't directly answered this question very successfully. This may
seem like bad news for semantics, but it is actually not that uncommon for the
basic concepts of a successful science to remain problematic: a physicist will
probably have trouble telling you what time is. The nature of meaning, and the
nature of time, are foundational questions that are debated by philosophers.
We
can simplify the problem a little by saying that, whatever meanings are, we are
interested in literal meaning.
Often, much more than the meaning of a sentence is conveyed when someone uses
it. Suppose that Carol says ‘I have to study’ in answer to ‘Can you go to the
movies tonight?’. She means that she has to study that night, and that this is
a reason why she can't go to the movies. But the sentence she used literally means only that she has to study.
Nonliteral meanings are studied in pragmatics, an area of linguistics that deals with discourse and
contextual effects.
But
what is a literal meaning? There are four sorts of answers: (1) you can dodge
the question, or (2) appeal to usage, or (3) appeal to psychology, or (4) treat
meanings as real objects.
(1)
The first idea would involve trying to reconstruct semantics so that it can be
done without actually referring to meanings. It turns out to be hard to do this
-- at least, if you want a theory that does what linguistic semanticists would
like a theory to do. But the idea was popular earlier in the twentieth century,
especially in the 1940s and 1950s, and has been revived several times since
then, because many philosophers would prefer to do without meanings if at all
possible. But these attempts tend to ignore the linguistic requirements, and
for various technical reasons have not been very successful.
(2)
When an English speaker says ‘It's raining’ and a French speaker says ‘Il
pleut’ you can say that there is a common pattern of usage here. But no one
really knows how to characterize what the two utterances have in common without
somehow invoking a common meaning. (In this case, the meaning that it's raining.)
So this idea doesn't seem to really explain what meanings are.
(3)
Here, you would try to explain meanings as ideas. This is an old idea, and is
still popular; nowadays, it takes the form of developing an artificial language
that is supposed to capture the "inner cognitive representations" of
an ideal thinking and speaking agent. The problem with this approach is that
the methods of contemporary psychology don't provide much help in telling us in
general what these inner representations are like. This idea doesn't seem yet
to lead to a methodology that can produce a workable semantic theory.
(4)
If you say that the meaning of ‘Mars’ is a certain planet, at least you have a
meaning relation that you can come to grips with. There is the word ‘Mars’ on the
one hand, and on the other hand there is this big ball of matter circling
around the sun. This clarity is good, but it is hard to see how you could cover
all of language this way. It doesn't help us very much in saying what sentences
mean, for instance. And what about the other meaning of ‘Mars’? Do we have to
believe in the Roman god to say that ‘Mars’ is meaningful? And what about ‘the
largest number’?
The
approach that most semanticists endorse is a combination of (1) and (4). Using
techniques similar to those used by mathematicians, you can build up a complex
universe of abstract objects that can serve as meanings (or denotations) of
various sorts of linguistic expressions. Since sentences can be either true or
false, the meanings of sentences usually involve the two truth values true and false. You can
make up artificial languages for talking about these objects; some semanticists
claim that these languages can be used to capture inner cognitive
representations. If so, this would also incorporate elements of (3), the
psychological approach to meanings. Finally, by restricting your attention to
selected parts of natural language, you can often avoid hard questions about
what meanings in general are. This is why this approach to some extent dodges
the general question of what meanings are. The hope would be, however, that as
more linguistic constructions are covered, better and more adequate
representations of meaning would emerge.
Though
"truth values" may seem artificial as components of meaning, they are
very handy in talking about the meaning of things like negation; the semantic
rule for negative sentences says that their meanings are like that of the
corresponding positive sentences, except that the truth value is switched, false for true and true for false. ‘It
isn't raining’ is true if ‘It is raining’ is false, and false if ‘It is
raining’ is true.
Truth
values also provide a connection to validity and
to valid reasoning. (It is valid to infer a sentence S2 from S1 in
case S2 couldn't possibly be true when S1 is false.) This interest in valid
reasoning provides a strong connection to work in the semantics of artificial
languages, since these languages are usually designed with some reasoning task
in mind. Logical languages are designed to model theoretical reasoning such as
mathematical proofs, while computer languages are intended to model a variety
of general and special purpose reasoning tasks. Validity is useful in working
with proofs because it gives us a criterion for correctness. It is useful in
much the same way with computer programs, where it can sometimes be used to
either prove a program correct, or (if the proof fails) to discover flaws in
programs.
These
ideas (which really come from logic) have proved to be very powerful in
providing a theory of how the meanings of natural-language sentences depend on
the meanings of the words they contain and their syntactic structure. Over the
last forty years or so, there has been a lot of progress in working this out,
not only for English, but for a wide variety of languages. This is made much
easier by the fact that human languages are very similarin the kinds of rules
that are needed for projecting meanings from words to sentences; they mainly
differ in their words, and in the details of their syntactic rules.
Recently,
there has been more interest in lexical semantics -- that is, in the semantics
of words. Lexical semantics is not so much a matter of trying to write an
"ideal dictionary". (Dictionaries contain a lot of useful
information, but don't really provide a theory of meaning or good
representations of meanings.) Rather, lexical semantics is concerned with
systematic relations in the meanings of words, and in recurring patterns among
different meanings of the same word. It is no accident, for instance, that you
can say ‘Sam ate a grape’ and ‘Sam ate’, the former saying what Sam ate and the
latter merely saying that Sam ate something. This same pattern occurs with many
verbs.
Logic
is a help in lexical semantics, but lexical semantics is full of cases in which
meanings depend subtly on context, and there are exceptions to many
generalizations. (To undermine something is to mine under it; but to understand
something is not to stand under it.) So logic doesn't carry us as far here as
it seems to carry us in the semantics of sentences.
Natural-language
semantics is important in trying to make computers better able to deal directly
with human languages. In one typical application, there is a program people
need to use. Running the program requires using an artificial language
(usually, a special-purpose command language or query-language) that tells the
computer how to do some useful reasoning or question-answering task. But it is
frustrating and time-consuming to teach this language to everyone who may want
to interact with the program. So it is often worthwhile to write a second
program, a natural language interface, that mediates between simple commands in
a human language and the artificial language that the computer understands.
Here, there is certainly no confusion about what a meaning is; the meanings you
want to attach to natural language commands are the corresponding expressions
of the programming language that the machine understands. Many computer
scientists believe that natural language semantics is useful in designing
programs of this sort. But it is only part of the picture. It turns out that
most English sentences are ambiguous to a depressing extent. (If a sentence has
just five words, and each of these words has four meanings, this alone gives
potentially 1,024 possible combined meanings.) Generally, only a few of these
potential meanings will be at all plausible. People are very good at focusing
on these plausible meanings, without being swamped by the unintended meanings.
But this takes common sense, and at present we do not have a very good idea of
how to get computers to imitate this sort of common sense. Researchers in the
area of computer science known as Artificial Intelligence are working on that.
Meanwhile, in building natural-language interfaces, you can exploit the fact
that a specific application (like retrieving answers from a database)
constrains the things that a user is likely to say. Using this, and other
clever techniques, it is possible to build special purpose natural-language
interfaces that perform remarkably well, even though we are still a long way
from figuring out how to get computers to do general-purpose natural-language
understanding.
Semantics probably won't help you find out the meaning of a
word you don't understand, though it does have a lot to say about the patterns
of meaningfulness that you find in words. It certainly can't help you
understand the meaning of one of Shakespeare's sonnets, since poetic meaning is
so different from literal meaning. But as we learn more about semantics, we are
finding out a lot about how the world's languages match forms to meanings. And
in doing that, we are learning a lot about ourselves and how we think, as well
as acquiring knowledge that is useful in many different fields and
applications.
No comments:
Post a Comment